De Minimis
  • Home
  • Podcast
  • Art
  • Get published!
  • ABOUT US
  • Comment Policy
  • Archive
    • 2018
    • 2017
    • 2017 >
      • Semester 2 (Volume 12) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8 (election issue)
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
    • 2016 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 9) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
      • Semester 2 (Volume 10) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8 (Election Issue)
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
        • Issue 13 (test)
    • 2015 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 7) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
      • Semester 2 (Volume 8) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
    • 2014 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 5) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
      • Semester 2 (Volume 6) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 12
    • 2013 >
      • Issue 1
      • Issue 2
      • Issue 3
      • Issue 4
      • Issue 5
      • Issue 6
    • 2012 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 1) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
      • Semester 2 (Volume 2) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
  • Blog

Original Stigma

3/9/2019

 
Issue 6, Semester 2, 2019

GRIMALDUS

TRIGGER WARNING: This article contains references to child sexual abuse and paedophilia.

The Supreme Court of Victoria’s recent decision to uphold the conviction of Cardinal George Pell for child sexual abuse has seen a (justified) outpouring of sympathy for Pell’s victims. This has been accompanied by a wave of public vitriol directed at the disgraced Prince of Rome. Be forewarned—this article will attempt to open up a conversation about the motivations for such acts, and argue for a shift in how they are commonly perceived.
Picture
Image: Wikimedia Commons

Undoubtedly, Pell’s crimes were a heinous violation of another, vulnerable human being. However, this isn’t an article about Pell. On the contrary, the public conflation of the term ‘paedophile’ with ‘child sex offender’ has created a situation in which the safe management of paedophilic urges is more difficult. Furthermore, the extreme, emotionally-charged vitriol reserved for child sex offenders above any other class of criminal has led to a political climate inhospitable to our higher ideals as a society.

I’m therefore left to take the rather unpopular position that Australia’s approach to paedophilia is not only counterproductive from a practical standpoint, but also unethical.  

A paedophile and a child sex offender are not the same thing. Paedophilia is a psychiatric condition—an attraction to prepubescent children. Not all paedophiles are child sex offenders, nor vice versa. However, for all the nuance present in public discourse, they might as well be one and the same. 

Nevertheless, if there is one group in society for whom the greatest opprobrium is reserved, it is ‘paedophiles’. Colloquial use of the term conflates the psychiatric condition with the very worst cases of child abduction, which has fed into a good old-fashioned moral panic about the supposed danger of today’s streets. 

I am not a psychiatrist, nor a philosopher, however as students of the law, I believe it incumbent upon us to question injustices we see around us. Is it just, then, to demonise someone for a mental characteristic; something they have no power over? 

Proudly commenting ‘we should just kill them’ on Facebook news stories (as some invariably do) is little more than virtue signalling. Such punitive proposals boil down to demonising the mentally ill, and should not be treated seriously.

On the contrary, our attitude of abject condemnation may endanger the safety of our children. If you were suffering from such an affliction, would you come forward? It certainly seems unwise to do so, given how likely it would be to destroy your social relationships, your employment opportunities, and put you at risk of violence. In some jurisdictions, it may even have legal consequences. No, it’s probably inadvisable to reach out to your support networks on this one. However, this means you will not receive the clinical assistance you might require, in order to keep your urges in check. Do we as a society really want to be screening out the opportunity to prevent harm? 

The harms resulting from paedophilia stem from the damage it causes the subjects of its attraction. In this manner it is distinguishable from, say, criminalised homosexuality, due to the possibility of a sufferer acting on their attraction in a manner damaging to a child. By definition, a child cannot consent to a sexual act. 

I have heard it said that paedophilia is inherently ‘deviant’ and thus ought not to be tolerated by society. However, the disgust one feels toward another’s sexual profile, so long as that person does not harm others, should be irrelevant to questions of legality. One might also draw the link between these arguments and historical justifications for any number of so called ‘vice laws.’ The criminalisation of homosexuality or alcohol, spring to mind.

Viewing paedophilia through the lens of mental illness, our treatment of child sex offenses bears reviewing.  In April of last year, the Berejiklian Government introduced a suite of reforms aimed at keeping child sex offenders incarcerated for longer. This might be laudable, if the intention of the reforms was to decrease such crimes in the community. 

Regrettably, the reforms seem only to pander to public fears, and are part of a trend of attacks against judicial discretion in sentencing enacted by legislatures across Australia. They are designed to be ‘tough’, without necessarily achieving their nominal purpose – the prevention of child sex abuse. 

Why do we feel compelled to lock up (if child sex offenders may be so termed) the criminally insane? I would suggest that it isn’t in order to rehabilitate, as there are far more appropriate settings to this end than prison. Nor should incarceration be justified purely as punishment, as this achieves nothing but to tickle our impulse for vengeance. Is it, then, to protect potential victims of such offenders?

These questions are illustrative of a broader penological debate: should our criminal justice system be geared towards deterrence, punishment, incapacitation, or rehabilitation? Our legal system is not designed to ask these questions, because they presuppose a politically uncomfortable reality - one in which human beings are not purely rational agents, able to be held solely accountable for their actions.

If we agree that the purpose of criminally sentencing child sex offenders is the protection of children, then it does not necessarily follow that such individuals should be locked away for years on end. Whilst it may seem counterintuitive, we must grapple with the reality that child sex offences have some of the lowest recidivism rates of any crime, barring murder.

This may indicate that once an intervention has been made in the life of an at-risk offender, we are generally quite competent at managing the issue. Rather than taking a punitive approach to this issue, perhaps it is time to adopt a more medically-oriented regime. Currently, some of the harshest penalties in Victoria are reserved for child sex offences. ‘So well they should’, you might say, but this is to ignore the substantive arguments of this article. Notwithstanding the issue of mental health, isn’t it preferable that people at risk of offending seek help, before it’s too late? 

I doubt that anyone reading this article would suggest that someone with depression poses a danger to others, such that they should be involuntarily committed. Rather, we recognise that with appropriate medical interventions, such conditions can be safely managed. However, in the past, such arguments were mounted on the basis that the committal of such individuals ensured the safety of society.

George Pell is seventy-eight years old. He will likely die in prison, after living out the span of his natural life behind bars. That is, if he isn’t murdered by a fellow inmate first; even other convicts apparently feel justified in looking down on ‘rock spiders’. 

I am not suggesting that in the case of George Pell, leniency should necessarily have been shown. However, I am calling for a shift in the way this issue is perceived and discussed. After all, there but for a quirk of nature, walks any one of us.

​Grimaldus is a First Year JD Student.
Hmmm
3/9/2019 11:42:12 pm

(Cw: mental illness and child sexual offences)

I really think the name for the psychiatric condition you're referring to should be changed, so there is a specific, more neutral word that refers to people who meet the DSM-5 criteria for the condition and are not offenders. The common usage of the term specifically connotes an offender, who has harmed children, so what you describe as 'moral panic' is totally justified. That usage is too socially entrenched to be changed and it seems far simpler to ask specialists to diagnose innocent patients with a differently-named condition.

Also, if you're right that not all people who meet the criteria for diagnosis with the psychiatric condition are offenders, the reverse almost certainly applies. I.e. many offenders would not meet the criteria for diagnosis. However, you seem to assume that people convicted of child sexual offences have this condition. I'm not sure why this article even refers to Pell, given that (as far as I'm aware) it has never been suggested he has a psychiatric condition.

Further, given that some people with the psychiatric condition do not offend, then the condition does NOT, on its own, explain the offending or erase someone's culpability. That is, a so-called 'quirk of nature' could not explain or exculpate the offending. And again, I don't think it has ever been claimed Pell has the relevant psychiatric condition.

In short, your own article seems to conflate child sex offenders with people who have a specific psychiatric condition. While it might be unhelpful to suggest that all people with the psychiatric condition are at risk of offending, it is dangerous and implausible to suggest that all offenders' behaviour can be viewed through a medical lens.


Shrek
4/9/2019 03:28:31 pm

"Is it just, then, to demonise someone for a mental characteristic; something they have no power over?"

The mental characteristic isn't being demonised when the courts sentence someone who has committed a child sexual offence though: the indecent act is. The courts's denunciation of paedophilia doesn't extend past the denunciation of paedophilic acts (which as you rightly pointed out can be conducted by people diagnosed with paedophilia as well as those not so diagnosed). A paedophile who is sentenced for child sexual offences might face a longer sentence on the basis that they are at higher risk of recidivism than people without such a diagnosis, but the sentence rests upon the practical ruling not the medical one. If a psychiatrist were to declare to the court that an offender who was NOT diagnosed with 'paedophilia' posed a higher risk of recidivism, a judge would not treat this evidence differently in sentencing than in a similar scenario where the same defendant had been diagnosed with the condition and posed the same risk of recidivism. The same can be said for the heinousness of an act - I could be wrong but I don't think the courts distinguish between the heinousness of an act committed by someone with the disorder and someone without the disorder.

As for society's 'demonisation' of paedophilia there is no question of whether it is just or fair. The fact that society condems something isn't really an injustice, it is just a social truth. By taking a certain stance on something society might be taking steps in a direction ultimately detrimental to itself, but this doesn't bring up questions of injustice as much as it does questions of practicality.

Lion IRC
5/9/2019 09:25:51 pm

Interesting observations about social constructs.
Ancient Greece hardly thought of 'the P word' as a mental illness and they would have deftly rebutted your claim..."by definition, a child cannot consent to a sexual act" by saying;
...well in that case, change the definition of "child"

We change the definition of words all the time these days.
Marriage. Person. Alive. Evidence. Reasonable. Doubt.


Comments are closed.
    Picture

    Archives

    September 2020
    August 2020
    July 2020
    June 2020
    May 2020
    April 2020
    March 2020
    February 2020
    October 2019
    September 2019
    August 2019
    July 2019
    May 2019
    April 2019
    March 2019
    February 2019
    October 2018
    September 2018
    August 2018
    July 2018
    May 2018
    April 2018
    March 2018
    February 2018
    October 2017
    September 2017
    August 2017
    July 2017
    June 2017
    May 2017
    April 2017
    March 2017
    February 2017
    November 2016
    October 2016
    September 2016
    August 2016
    July 2016
    May 2016
    April 2016
    March 2016
    February 2016
    December 2015
    October 2015
    September 2015
    August 2015
    May 2015
    April 2015
    March 2015
    October 2014
    September 2014
    August 2014
    July 2014
    May 2014
    April 2014

  • Home
  • Podcast
  • Art
  • Get published!
  • ABOUT US
  • Comment Policy
  • Archive
    • 2018
    • 2017
    • 2017 >
      • Semester 2 (Volume 12) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8 (election issue)
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
    • 2016 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 9) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
      • Semester 2 (Volume 10) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8 (Election Issue)
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
        • Issue 13 (test)
    • 2015 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 7) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
      • Semester 2 (Volume 8) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
    • 2014 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 5) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
      • Semester 2 (Volume 6) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 12
    • 2013 >
      • Issue 1
      • Issue 2
      • Issue 3
      • Issue 4
      • Issue 5
      • Issue 6
    • 2012 >
      • Semester 1 (Volume 1) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
      • Semester 2 (Volume 2) >
        • Issue 1
        • Issue 2
        • Issue 3
        • Issue 4
        • Issue 5
        • Issue 6
        • Issue 7
        • Issue 8
        • Issue 9
        • Issue 10
        • Issue 11
        • Issue 12
  • Blog